3 Discoveries in Mathematics That Will Change How You See The World

Поделиться
HTML-код
  • Опубликовано: 25 фев 2023
  • Discover the weird and wonderful world of math! Learn about the Monty Hall Problem, the Nash Equilibrium, and the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Math. Could math be an inaccurate representation of reality? Find out now!
    Biographics: / @biographics
    Geographics: / @geographicstravel
    Warographics: / @warographics643
    MegaProjects: / @megaprojects9649
    Into The Shadows: / intotheshadows
    TopTenz: / toptenznet
    Today I Found Out: / todayifoundout
    Highlight History: / @highlighthistory
    Business Blaze: / @brainblaze6526
    Casual Criminalist: / thecasualcriminalist
    Decoding the Unknown: / @decodingtheunknown2373

Комментарии • 3,6 тыс.

  • @alanscottholmes8913
    @alanscottholmes8913 Год назад +1367

    My dad used to always say there's 3 types of people in this world.. Those that can count and those that can't.... Very important life lesson I think 🤔

    • @aceundead4750
      @aceundead4750 Год назад +36

      Yours too? That's 2 now let's see if we can get a third person whose dad didnt say that and see who can count.

    • @IrishMike22
      @IrishMike22 Год назад +85

      All 3 of my dads would say that

    • @anttikalpio4577
      @anttikalpio4577 Год назад

      There are 10 types of people in the world. Those who understand binary and those who don’t.

    • @waynebimmel6784
      @waynebimmel6784 Год назад

      There's 1 types of people, those who know binary and those who don't.

    • @techn1kal1ty
      @techn1kal1ty Год назад +18

      That's deeper than it seems

  • @storkbomb7417
    @storkbomb7417 Год назад +565

    The keys to understanding The Monty Hall Problem are realizing that the host knows which curtain hides the winner, and that when he opens a curtain, he'll always choose to reveal one of the losers (otherwise it'd ruin the game, right?)
    When you choose one of the three curtains at the beginning, you are also deciding which two curtains the host can choose from when it's his turn to open one. If you pick the winner initally (a 1 in 3 chance), he'll have two losers to pick from, and if you pick one of the losers (a 2 in 3 chance), he'll have one loser and one winner to pick from (being forced to pick the loser as stated above).
    So when he opens one of the remaining curtains and reveals the loser, there's a 2 in 3 chance he was forced to do so (because the other curtain that you didn't chose initially is the winner), meaning 2 in 3 times you chose a loser at the beginning. So yeah, you should switch.
    EDIT: I love the pedants insisting on applying real game show logic to a math problem: I get it, Monty could have not followed the rules. I can only imagine you in grade school: "ACKSHUALLY MRS SMITH, if Ralphie had 5 Pennies and gave 2 to Suzie, he would have 4 left because he likely palmed one!"

    • @charitysweetcharity3091
      @charitysweetcharity3091 Год назад +48

      Ah! Now it makes sense! Thanks:)

    • @qu1nsta
      @qu1nsta Год назад +34

      Exactly! Really well explained

    • @theoverunderthinker
      @theoverunderthinker Год назад +25

      great explanation. I was just thinking that since he is not going to show you the winner, and he is not going to show the one you picked, so seems that there was a good chance that he was forced to show the one he did.
      so I was on the right track, but your explanation clearly explained the why while I was only circling around the edges of the reason!
      nicely done.

    • @diracflux
      @diracflux Год назад +12

      Wonderful explanation, it makes complete sense now. Thanks!

    • @Ender7j
      @Ender7j Год назад +22

      This. This explains it. Thank you. Now I understand why the probabilities change the way they do…too bad my stats teacher couldn’t have used this in class…

  • @fleetadmiralj
    @fleetadmiralj Год назад +168

    I actually kind of like the way Mythbusters explained the Monty Hall problem. If you consider your door is a 1/3 chance and the other two doors are a combined 2/3 chance, the fact that one of those doors is opened doesn't change the fact that they are a combined 2/3 chance.

    • @djtjm7000
      @djtjm7000 Год назад +19

      Wait a minute. Combined they have a 2/3 chance. Break them up and they don't each retain a 2/3 chance of winning! The pairing is arbitrary.
      Option 1. Say you have two picks. The first pick has a 1/3 chance of being right. If you were wrong, your second pick would have a 50% chance of being right. Regardless of which one you pick. In total you had a 2/3 chance of winning. The doors could have been 2 red and 1 blue door or 2 blue and 1 red door. It doesn't matter how they are paired.
      Option 2. You can pick one door or pick a pair of doors. Naturally you would pick a pair of doors (say #2 & #3) because that would also give you a 2/3 chance of winning. Then the host says surprise, door three just disappears, it's gone. So does the 1/3 chance that that door being the winner. I don't see why the 1/3 chance that door three had would transfer to the remaining door in your pair, any more than it would transfer to door number 1. There are no transfer of odds.

    • @catowarmeowson9964
      @catowarmeowson9964 Год назад +3

      The fact that the host won't show you if you win ruins that

    • @fleetadmiralj
      @fleetadmiralj Год назад +39

      @@djtjm7000 It actually does matter because the door that is shown the contestant is *always* a loser door. If it were random, you might be right, but it's not. And that's why this math trick is deceptive. People act like the last two doors are a 50/50 chance because they act like the elimination of the first door is random *but it's not*.
      If you picked a winning door, the eliminated door will be a loser because both other doors are losers. But if you picked a losing door, the remaining door that doesn't get opened *is always the winning door*. Given there is a 2/3 chance you picked a losing door to begin with, there is a 2/3 chance the remaining door is the winning door, because the door that gets opened is not random.

    • @cocoavideos
      @cocoavideos Год назад +10

      @@djtjm7000 I tend to agree with you. When one door is removed, the odds remaining turn into 50/50 that I picked correctly the first time versus the remaining door. I would argue that the 1/3 that got removed gets split into the two remaining doors, since we don't know which of them is the winning door. It is kind of like flipping a penny. You flip it 9 times and it comes heads (unlikely but possible, presuming 50/50 change heads/tails). The next flip still has a 50/50 chance of coming heads.

    • @DennisSullivan-om3oo
      @DennisSullivan-om3oo Год назад +2

      You explained it better than Simon.

  • @dzk33
    @dzk33 Год назад +50

    Another way to look at the Monty Hall problem is that it's effectively the same as giving you the option of sticking with your original choice or changing to selecting both other doors.

    • @davemates6624
      @davemates6624 Год назад +3

      My favourite explanation as well. Or in the case of 100 doors, the choice is keep your 1 door or choose all of the 99 other doors.

    • @TheGraemeEvans
      @TheGraemeEvans Год назад

      Totally agree

    • @glennifer1225
      @glennifer1225 Год назад +2

      That’s a great insight

    • @boffo63
      @boffo63 Год назад

      Alright, I can live with that. But people want to believe in their luck so that's where my problem was.

    • @superkingoftacos2920
      @superkingoftacos2920 Год назад +2

      Exactly. It doesn't matter when you decide to switch, the probability locks in when you choose the door. 1/3 you're right and 2/3 chance you're wrong. Switching is basically just saying: I think it's not the one I picked first.

  • @williamwhalen746
    @williamwhalen746 Год назад +307

    This video hit close to home. Being color-blind in the green-red spectrum, I can't count the number of times that I have attempted to explain what the world looks like to me. People are often surprised to find that to me the world looks perfectly normal for it is the only way that I have ever seen it. I was told that certain color was green and therefore I call it green. The odds are my green differs from your green. The best way to explain how my vision varies is to show its' impact. For instance, showing up for a dress-green uniform inspection in the military wearing blue suit pants (yes, I really did that.)

    • @khironkinney1667
      @khironkinney1667 Год назад +3

      The questions posed in this in regards colorblindness I totally understand my best friend has proposed the prospective situation. What his of green perception to my green there's no way to confirm or deny that.

    • @khironkinney1667
      @khironkinney1667 Год назад +10

      The trouble with explaining colorblindness to people is that Certain Shade blend together there are certain shades of green very light look yellow to me are things like moss which are red sort of green throwing some Ferns and I can't find my golf discs

    • @robinbaylor2672
      @robinbaylor2672 Год назад

      That happened to a co-worker of mine, too.

    • @duanesamuelson2256
      @duanesamuelson2256 Год назад +7

      There are women who have 4 different cones..

    • @egondro9157
      @egondro9157 Год назад +7

      @@khironkinney1667 I have know idea what you wrote. It is extremely hard to understand. I would recommend either editing it with correct grammar and punctuation. Otherwise if English isn’t your first language then just write in the language your best in.

  • @davidhayden4743
    @davidhayden4743 Год назад +97

    The Monty Hall problem is that your choice of curtain is random - the hosts choice to show you is NOT random. The host never shows you your curtain OR the curtain with the $1,000,000. It's the combination of non-random and random variables that causes most of the confusion.

    • @insignificantfool8592
      @insignificantfool8592 Год назад +5

      Yeah, it especially causes confusion if those assumptions you're stating are not even mentioned. Why do I have to go along with these assumptions then?

    • @tolkienfan1972
      @tolkienfan1972 Год назад +7

      I agree... When Monty opens a curtain he is revealing information.

    • @Demmrir
      @Demmrir Год назад +3

      @@insignificantfool8592 It doesn't actually depend on those factors though. By choosing a door, you yourself are fixing a condition. The fact that one of the doors doesn't contain the goat that was chosen while you were holding a door means the odds are now 2:3 for the last goat. This is irrespective of the fact the host will never open your door or the goat's door.

    • @insignificantfool8592
      @insignificantfool8592 Год назад +2

      @@Demmrir many people think so, but it's not true. Imagine the host really doesn't want the contestant to win the car (maybe he has to pay for the prizes himself and is low on cash). What exactly prevents him from opening the contestant's door if he chose a goat door and only offer the switch when he chose the car door?

    • @rickh9396
      @rickh9396 Год назад +4

      The tendency to stick with one's original choice is also reinforced by the contestant assuming that the host knows he or she chose the $1 million and is intentionally trying to throw him or her off. The other assumption being that if you had chosen wrong, he wouldn't give you an opportunity to change your mind.

  • @TROOPERfarcry
    @TROOPERfarcry Год назад +12

    In the Monty-Hall problem, _the host does _*_not_*_ choose randomly._
    ... and that's it. That's the one thing that changes *everything.*

    • @fudhater8592
      @fudhater8592 5 дней назад

      And it's irrelevant to the question

    • @TROOPERfarcry
      @TROOPERfarcry 5 дней назад

      @@fudhater8592 It wasn't a question, it was a statement.... in a video about statements.
      Thank you for trying to sound smart at my expense. Better luck next time.

    • @fudhater8592
      @fudhater8592 5 дней назад

      @@TROOPERfarcry It's irrelevant to the question of "What are the odds if you stay or switch". Try to keep up

    • @TROOPERfarcry
      @TROOPERfarcry 5 дней назад

      @@fudhater8592 You're like a smartass, _hold-the-smart._ If you eat enough fiber to dislodge your head from your rectum, you'll realize that in order for the Monty Hall problem to work, the host has to know where the prize is. IE, it's not random.
      Do try to keep up, dear.

  • @mikem5149
    @mikem5149 24 дня назад +1

    They missed the key point: The host knows and will never show the big prize. Therefore, you have no new information. You’re simply being asked if you want to switch your 1/3 guess to 2/3.

  • @joshm3484
    @joshm3484 Год назад +88

    Great explanation of the Monty Hall problem. I think it's so confusing because it _isn't_ a pure maths problem. The host doesn't pick a door at random, but people intuitively assume it's random chance.

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg Год назад +4

      It doesn't matter what the host chooses to reveal if it's a fair game, though. In the video's example, you still either chose the $1M or the banana, it's not like the banana was what was revealed. The remaining 2 curtains becomes that psychological poison chalice dilemma with the host at that point. It would only be unfair odds if the host can cheat by changing what prize was behind the chosen curtain when asking if you're sure.

    • @schwarzerritter5724
      @schwarzerritter5724 Год назад +17

      Simon's explanation is wrong. He said: "He [the host] reveals that concealed behind curtain number 3 is a thousand dollars", but he did not establish that the host always reveals a curtain. That is actually a huge difference, because without this additional information, the problem is unsolvable. The host could always reveal a curtain, he could reveal a curtain because you guessed right and it is too early for someone to win the main prince. Many versions of the Monty Hall problem make this mistake.

    • @davidioanhedges
      @davidioanhedges Год назад +38

      The host knows which curtain hides the million, and he will never open this curtain, and he will never reveal what's behind the curtain you chose, so there are three scenarios :
      1 : If you chose the Million - he can reveal what's behind either of the other curtains at random - if you change you lose
      2 : If you chose the Thousand - he can *only* reveal the Banana - if you change you win
      3 : if you chose the Banana - he can *only* reveal the thousand - if you change you win
      He has knowledge and restricted choices, so what is revealed does change the odds ..

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg Год назад +1

      @@davidioanhedges The problem with your idea is there will never be a 2nd curtain reveal out of 3. If the 1st one revealed shows $1000, what's the 2nd reveal going to show? If it reveals the $1M, you choose the revealed $1M. If it reveals the banana, you choose the only unrevealed curtain remaining since it will be the $1M.

    • @FranzBiscuit
      @FranzBiscuit Год назад +6

      @@davidioanhedges Precisely.

  • @ignitionfrn2223
    @ignitionfrn2223 Год назад +25

    0:45 - Chapter 1 - The monty hall problem
    4:30 - Chapter 2 - The nash equilibrium
    11:30 - Chapter 3 - Math might not be real

  • @olanmills64
    @olanmills64 Год назад +29

    I think an intuitive way to understand the Monty Hall problem is this: The chances that your initial pick is correct are low (1 in 3). So when Monty reveals an empty door and you have the option to pick the other one, you're basically being asked, "What are the chances that you blindly picked the winner on the first try?" They're not good, so it's likely the one remaining is the winner, and so you should switch

    • @joesterling4299
      @joesterling4299 Год назад +9

      Or, Monty doesn't want to give away a million bucks, so he shows you a sure thing after you picked the best door, hoping you'll switch and save him $999,000.

    • @egrace3738
      @egrace3738 Год назад

      Now, this example I understand! Thanks

    • @strifera
      @strifera Год назад +3

      The problem with that intuitive way to understand the problem is it's not actually understanding the problem. If the empty door is arbitrarily revealed, there's no advantage in switching. The door not containing the prize isn't the only thing that factors into why it's advantageous to switch.

    • @abrahambashaija5405
      @abrahambashaija5405 Год назад +1

      But the 2/3 probability of the second door is also not good

    • @olanmills64
      @olanmills64 Год назад +2

      @@strifera yes, of course, this is assuming knowledge of how the show always works, which is fair to assume in this case. That's part of the stated problem, and it's an event that is repeated every time on the show. The host always knowingly picks an empty door to reveal

  • @TheRunescapeians
    @TheRunescapeians Год назад +1

    This explanation of Monty Hall leaves out the key detail that the host knows which door the grand prize is behind and will never choose to show you that door. If that assumption isn't true, it doesn't matter whether or not you switch.

  • @anasyn
    @anasyn Год назад +62

    I think the funniest example of a Nash Equilibrium is when two people approach each other while walking around a corner. Both frighten each other and for whatever reason both step to the left and both step to the right at the same exact time. This is actually the opposite of the equilibrium. The correct method would be to converse with the other participant and say "Go to the right" or just grab them by the shoulders and do a 180 degree spin with them so neither can get confused. My method is that whenever this happens to me my first and only instinct, instead of getting stuck in the dumb left right left right loop of laughter and embarrassment, is to stand directly upright and perfectly still like a deer in the headlights. It freaks the other person out which makes them go around me faster, but also leaves no room for guesswork and they know that my intention is to let them go around me in whichever direction they want.

    • @VosperCDN
      @VosperCDN Год назад +4

      Not sure where it falls, but my default is to stand still and let the other person move around me. Saves a bit of time, but I lose out on the two-step shuffle dance moves.

    • @jamienorris007
      @jamienorris007 Год назад +4

      My theory is most people will step to the dominant side. That being the right hand side as most people are right handed. So my question is are you ambidextrous???

    • @briancherry8088
      @briancherry8088 Год назад +19

      This is a Canadian stalemate. Both wants to move for the other and not look rude, so we spend hours just going back and forth saying "you first, no you first, no I insist you first". And "sorry. No I'm sorry."

    • @JohnRandomness105
      @JohnRandomness105 Год назад +2

      If you're going in the opposite direction, it works fine when both step to the right or to the left. It only fails if one person steps to the right and the other steps to the left.

    • @jedaaa
      @jedaaa Год назад

      I just grab them by the scruff of the neck and beat the living daylights out of them, then I turn around and walk back the way I came from, it's far from ideal but who's perfect right

  • @thecommenternobodycaresabout
    @thecommenternobodycaresabout Год назад +15

    "Math is perfect, real life is not" a very beautiful quote the represents the reality. Here is an example: I studied electronics and since I love playing bass, I decided to make an amplifier from scratch. I even got specialized equipment like an oscilloscope to get the best idea of what's going on. Here is what I found out: the equations that are supposed to give you the results of your circuit are simply not correct. Of course some *DO* give you the results you should expect after doing the math but things were acting very weird to the point I gave up because they made no sense and I didn't know how to proceed to complete it. Multisim, a program that allows digital simulation of a circuit would give me errors all the time because it, just like me, just couldn't comprehend wtf is going on there. The circuit outputted about 3% of what I wanted and since it wasn't any major project or something, I simply gave up and left it for when I have the will to complete it, at some point in the future, hopefully.
    Before you blame me, I am confident that the circuit was correct. Only faulty parts could have been the reason for this but I just bought them and they were brand new, so, I don't know.

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад +1

      whelp, atleast you got your name right.

    • @aralbrec
      @aralbrec Год назад +2

      The circuit output 3% of what you expected? Well that is you :)
      Circuit theory is only an approximation of circuit behaviour. V=IR, I=C dv/dt, V = L di/dt, KVL, KCL, etc are all only valid given assumptions about the size of the circuit, no interference from outside, and the speed of stimulus. They don't even describe the physical processes that lead to those quasi-steady state conditions described by those equations.
      A similar thing is going on with mathematical models describing semiconductor behaviour. They are simplified approximations whose equations are only considered valid when corresponding assumptions are valid. A single device can have multiple equations modelling behaviour and you can make the model more or less accurate at the expense of complexity.
      The models that humans use to design with are broadly simplified and will get you in the right ballpark. Computer simulation can use more complicated models and get you closer still. But this is before manufacturing variability is factored in, not to mention environmental factors that you may not be aware of or choose to ignore.
      Long story short, designs are broadly correct if your assumptions are correct but building something in the environment it is intended to operate in is always necessary to make sure things operate as intended and something(s) hasn't been overlooked. Getting an output 3% of expected is a significant error someplace. If everyone's designs were 97% off, it would be a fluke that anything worked. Electronic design would be more like witchcraft and the models used would be essentially worthless.

  • @danberm1755
    @danberm1755 Год назад +6

    I think that the main thing that people who explain the Monte Hall problem never really pin down into simple words is that Monte Hall would NEVER open the door to the million dollar prize on purpose.
    That is critical to the problem and I've never seen anyone explain the problem and mention that. Anyone who has seen the show automatically knows this critical detail.

    • @KpxUrz5745
      @KpxUrz5745 5 месяцев назад

      Oh? I've read numerous examples just today, where people point out that Monte would never open the big prize door.

    • @barryschwarz
      @barryschwarz 16 дней назад

      I don't understand wy the words "game show" don't automatically infer this to people. In what game show in the world is the big prize given away at random?

  • @stuartlovett
    @stuartlovett Год назад +13

    In The Monty Hall Problem, if you imagine the steps in the game taking place in a different order, the probabilities become clearer to see. Imagine that the host asks you to pick one of three curtains. After you pick one she simply says you can have the prize behind the curtain you picked, or the best prize that lies behind the other two curtains. I think most people would intuitively pick the “best prize behind two curtains” over the “prize behind one curtain”.
    Considering this in the context of the actual order of things in the game, the host knows where the big prize is and will never open that curtain. After the host opens that curtain, when the player chooses to switch it seems like they are choosing the prize behind one of two remaining curtains, but actually they are still choosing the “the best prize that lies behind the other two curtains”.
    I like when the problem is extrapolated to the 100 curtains. It becomes easier to see. Will you take the prize behind the curtain you picked or the best prize that lies behind the other 99 curtains?

    • @twilightstar1895
      @twilightstar1895 Год назад

      Excellent explanation

    • @cryptoslacker-464
      @cryptoslacker-464 Год назад

      You did the best explanation but I'm still confused 😆

    • @JebediahKerb
      @JebediahKerb Год назад

      Excellent explanation. I've always stuck with "yeah nah it's now 50/50", even after watching the video, but 10 minutes ago something happened in my brain and something made sense but I didn't know why. This explained it well.

    • @scottparker1741
      @scottparker1741 26 дней назад

      Pretty bad explanation here

  • @juliusx9953
    @juliusx9953 Год назад +65

    Probably one of my favorite SP videos so far, great Job from Simon and Team. I'd love to see more content on rather complicated topics like this.

  • @ilajoie3
    @ilajoie3 Год назад +60

    What, Simon actually watched a movie?
    We need to start making a list of the movies he's actually admitted to watching

    • @alyssinwilliams4570
      @alyssinwilliams4570 Год назад +24

      new channel for him: CinemaGraphics

    • @toddlerj102
      @toddlerj102 Год назад +1

      @@alyssinwilliams4570 lol

    • @toddlerj102
      @toddlerj102 Год назад +1

      That can't be more than the third time I've heard that from Simon. Although thousands of times it's wtf? Lol

    • @skwervin1
      @skwervin1 Год назад

      All 3of them!

  • @JohnRoach-jn4dg
    @JohnRoach-jn4dg 9 часов назад

    Solve the Monty Hall Paradox by adding a second candidate to play for the Grand Prize. Neither contestant chooses the Booby Prize. Monty Hall opens the door to reveal the Booby Prize. It is guaranteed that one of the two contestants has chosen the Grand Prize, but that contestant is advised to "switch"

  • @aedwa021
    @aedwa021 Год назад +18

    What helps me understand the Monty Hall problem is looking at it like "I have a 1/3 chance to pick the correct door on the first try and a 2/3 chance to have picked the wrong door." The 100 door example really helps too, such an extreme case makes it a lot more clear.

    • @DennisSullivan-om3oo
      @DennisSullivan-om3oo Год назад

      Andrew Well, it helps some people.

    • @DennisSullivan-om3oo
      @DennisSullivan-om3oo Год назад

      @@SigFigNewton Or if they know it, they don't see that they selective revelation creates a sampling bias. I am not proud, I admit that it took me a long time to understand it.

    • @scottparker1741
      @scottparker1741 26 дней назад

      I don’t think you understand the Monty problem

    • @joeelliott2157
      @joeelliott2157 24 дня назад +1

      By which you mean, I think, that if Monty Hall always opens 98 doors, none of which have $ 1,000,000, then it is more intuitively obvious that you should switch.

    • @MaviLeb
      @MaviLeb День назад

      You could also just list all the possible situations you can end up in after you have chosen your door and the host has revealed a door:
      Door in [] is chosen, door in || is revealed by the host, L looser door and W winner door. Assuming the host always opens a looser door, we get these cases:
      1. [L] |L| W
      2. [L] W |L|
      3a. [W] |L| L
      3b. [W] L |L|
      Now, we can say that 3a and 3b are the same and count them as one single case, because the order of the remaining doors (the L's) doesn't matter in this case.
      This leaves us with 3 cases. 2 of which switching would lead to you winning and one which wouldn't. This is how you can reach the 2/3 probability of winning by switching.
      Edit:
      Another way too look at it, is that you have 2/3 probability to chose one of the L's at first. And whenever you have chosen one of those L's, you're in case 1 or 2. Thus, switching wins in 2/3 of all cases.

  • @sbcee2220
    @sbcee2220 Год назад +55

    Best SideProjects I've seen in a while. Not that your other SPs weren't good, just that this one was amazing.
    Thanks, Simon!

    • @billflood50
      @billflood50 Год назад

      Agreed. This was very solid.

  • @eddie8900
    @eddie8900 Год назад +5

    Your explanation of the Nash Equilibrium is spot on. Every time the traffic lights outside my work break down, there's a nail biting display of idiocy which always results in someone crashing their car.

  • @martindim7182
    @martindim7182 2 дня назад

    "... changing your choice works more often than not". Exactly!!
    I know this is a year old video. The first time I heard this "variable change" problem was in the movie 21 (with Kevin Spacey). It struck me immediately as both interesting and weird. After thinking about it for a while I understood the theory behind it and that if you play it out 100 times, it's likely you will win the million 66.7 % of the time.
    The weird part of this problem for me is that the game show contestant does not have the luxury of playing it out 100 times. He or she has only one attempt at this. And therefore the chance of winning is exactly 50/50.
    From Monty Hall's point of view, since he has played this game hundreds of times, he loves it when people stay with their original choice. This way he saves money in the long run.

  • @i7voskilli560
    @i7voskilli560 Год назад +11

    Watching this after a 12 hour shift and being told maths might not be real, I’m too tired my brain hurts

    • @aceundead4750
      @aceundead4750 Год назад +2

      You probably shouldn't watch videos on the channels Stand-Up Maths or Dr Brian Keatong after a 12 hr shift then either lol

    • @MijinLaw
      @MijinLaw 26 дней назад

      The way I'd look at it is that much of mathematics is a toolkit for manipulating information. But not in arbitrary ways; the manipulations have to follow various properties like being self consistent and following deductive logic. It's not surprising that tools for deriving information -- essentially augmenting our intuitive reasoning -- would be useful.
      And then, further to this, the question of whether maths will always be useful comes down to whether our universe has properties like self consistency. Well, if it doesn't, then all bets are off.

  • @golferorb
    @golferorb Год назад +42

    I gotta be honest. This is one of my favorite videos you've ever made, Simon. Not really sure why but it's very interesting.

    • @randal_gibbons
      @randal_gibbons Год назад +2

      Because he's let us know that while we may not know how to calculate the velocity of a baseball, our brains are fully aware of how the baseball is moving.

  • @Ddonaldson9
    @Ddonaldson9 8 дней назад

    "This problem is pretty easy to understand if you have it explained to you in the best way" and then you proceed to explain it in not the best way.

  • @rolandfisher
    @rolandfisher 11 дней назад

    Monty Hall works better with a different frame on it. You have a hundred doors, and you make your pick. Good 'ol Monty asks, what are the odds you're right? You say 1%. He then says, "Want to switch?" You say, "No, thank you, I have no new information." He says, what if I remove half the wrong doors?" "I'm not sure." "What if I remove all the other wrong doors but one?" "Hell yeah, I'll switch. Thanks for the inside info, Monty."

  • @the-chillian
    @the-chillian Год назад +17

    I once thought I'd prove the right answer to the Monty Hall problem to myself once and for all by writing a simulation and running it a bunch of times to see how the probabilities landed -- but once I wrote it, I didn't have to run it at all. The answer jumped out at me from the code while writing the step where the host opens a door. I ended up with 3 cases to account for: the one where the contestant picked the right answer -- in which case it didn't matter which other door I picked -- and the two cases where they picked the wrong door, in which case there was no choice about which door to open because the rules allowed for only one of them. In only one of those scenarios would switching be the wrong choice; in the other two it would be right.

    • @ghaznavid
      @ghaznavid Год назад +1

      Same here. I also thought it was wrong when I first heard it, wrote a computer simulation, and had figured out the same thing before I even hit run.

    • @insignificantfool8592
      @insignificantfool8592 Год назад +1

      You can't put the two stage MH problem into code, since we don't know what the host will decide to do. How do you model the host's decision as to whether to open the player's door or whether to offer a switch?

    • @ghaznavid
      @ghaznavid Год назад +1

      ​@@insignificantfool8592 the host knows which door is the winning door. If you picked the winning door, then the eliminated door is irrelevant. If you didn't then there's only one door that can be eliminated. So basically your code is - identify which 2 doors are left, if the first isn't the winning one, eliminate it, if it is, eliminate the other non-selected one.

    • @insignificantfool8592
      @insignificantfool8592 Год назад +1

      @Jonathan Newman that would be assuming the host always has to offer the switch. That was not mentioned and thus shouldn't be assumed.

    • @ghaznavid
      @ghaznavid Год назад +2

      @@insignificantfool8592 the premise of the problem is that the switch is always offered.

  • @disorganizedorg
    @disorganizedorg Год назад +16

    You mention Richard Hamming in the "Maths may not be real segment" - he's well known in computer science circles for the development of error detection and correction algorithms, the descendants of which are used in computers & data communications to this day. Wikipedia has an article on these, named for him:
    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hamming_code

    • @anthonymonge7815
      @anthonymonge7815 Год назад +2

      I use the Hamming Distance in anomaly detection frameworks. Uncanny how it works!

  • @charlesglidden557
    @charlesglidden557 Год назад +1

    Monty Hall you left out dome rules : Host will ALWAYS show a second curtain weather or not you have the correct one : Host will never revile the big prize.

  • @VoteLaborOut
    @VoteLaborOut 2 месяца назад +1

    Instead of three, imagine there 10 doors.
    You pick one first, chance of picking right is 1/10. (The door is not revealed yet as that could end the show.)
    The chance of the prize behind the remaining doors is 9/10.
    The host opens 8 out of the remaining 9 doors, none of the 8 would be the prize. (The host knows where the prize is and revealing the prize would end the show.)
    Now the host basically eliminated the 8 wrong choices out of the 9 doors. The chance of the one remaining door the host did not open being the prize is very high (90%).
    The host basically just show us the answer and you should switch to that one remaining door.

  • @justinmckean
    @justinmckean Год назад +7

    This video is gold and I plan to show it again and again in my classes. (HS maths teacher) Your work continues to be so very good and awesome.

  • @esspyarrow8772
    @esspyarrow8772 Год назад +43

    This was a great presentation, Simon. I also quite enjoy this format so much. Thanks for all you do : )

  • @KpxUrz5745
    @KpxUrz5745 5 месяцев назад +2

    Savvy and slightly sarcastic gamblers have a saying, "Don't bet on anything that talks". Well, that's that's the problem with the Monty Hall Problem. Rather than strictly being a math or statistics problem, it confuses things by including Monty, without explaining anything about his consistency or motives.

  • @robedwards1720
    @robedwards1720 3 дня назад

    The reason people won't change from their original choice in the Monty Hall theory is that they are scared of the humiliation they perceive if the jackpot was indeed behind the one they originally picked

  • @PKF374
    @PKF374 Год назад +5

    You can think about the probability of prizes problem as your original choice keeps the same probability as when you selected, but the probability of the other doors gets added together and placed on the door not revealed.

    • @dudeinoakland
      @dudeinoakland Год назад

      The confusion becomes, why doesn't that same probability exist for the door selected first? Why does revealing one door increase the probability of only the door not selected?

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад +1

      @@dudeinoakland It doesn't. Whoever thinks that revealing one door gives you better chances if you change your mind is delusional

    • @JonMartinYXD
      @JonMartinYXD Год назад

      @@dudeinoakland The key to understanding the problem is that _the prize does not move._ Starting out, there are X doors (where X = 3 in the classic problem), each with a prize probability of 1/X. All the doors are in one group and the probability of the prize being behind a door in that group is 1. However as soon as you choose a door, you have split the doors into two groups: we will call them C (door you chose) and R (the doors you rejected). There is only one door in group C, so the probability of the prize being in C is 1/X. There are X - 1 doors in R, so the probability of the prize being in R is (X - 1)/X. No matter which doors in R the host opens the probabilities of the two groups remain as they were, 1/X for C and (X-1)/X for R, because _the prize does not move._ Eventually there will be only one door left unopened in group R so that door must have the same probability of having the prize as group R does (and always had).

    • @martinsoltau6926
      @martinsoltau6926 Год назад

      @@dudeinoaklandyou literally can switch from your initial one door to both the other doors and Monty also shows you, which of the other two doors is a loss.

  • @bretmcdanel8595
    @bretmcdanel8595 Год назад +7

    The monty hall problem can be better described as you pick door 1. The others are grouped together. [1] [2, 3]. The fact that door 3 gets revealed does not change that grouping. Visually grouping [2, 3] seems to help explain it better for most people.

    • @johndaniel7161
      @johndaniel7161 Год назад +3

      I think he must have explained it wrong, because the way he showed it still comes out to a 50/50 choice, by my calculations.
      Step 1. Pick between three.
      Step 2. Throw that choice in the garbage because it doesn't matter.
      Step 3. Pick between two.

    • @bretmcdanel8595
      @bretmcdanel8595 Год назад +2

      @@johndaniel7161 the odds don't change because an incorrect choice is revealed. That is why grouping visually helps explain.
      [1] [2, 3], odds of 1 are 33.3%, odds of 2 or 3 are 66.7% because they are grouped. Revealing 3 is a goat does not change the odds, 1 remains 33% and the group is 66% even though one in the group is invalid.

    • @bretmcdanel8595
      @bretmcdanel8595 Год назад +1

      ​@@johndaniel7161 I should add that the host knows which is the winning choice and which are the non-winning choices. When the host reveals a door in the grouped set they intentionally and knowingly reveal a non-winning choice (which actually matters a bit).

    • @iskierka8399
      @iskierka8399 Год назад

      @@bretmcdanel8595 It technically does not matter if the host revealed a winning choice, if the format was still "Do you want the best prize from among the doors you did not pick?", it would just make a bad gameshow - because that's what the host is *actually* asking, just phrased to hide it, and why the grouping helps. You're not being given a chance to switch within two doors, you're being given the chance to pick the best from two thirds of the doors, just you already know one of them is a dud.

    • @Horvath_Gabor
      @Horvath_Gabor Год назад +1

      @@iskierka8399 But that's kind of the point. The host can't do that, because it's against the rules of the game. When you're playing blackjack, the dealer cannot refuse to deal you a card, because then the game cannot commence. Similarly, the game host cannot reveal the winning door, because then the game is over. It's because the rules are set in stone that this is a mathematics problem instead of a sociology experiment.

  • @bjorneriksson6480
    @bjorneriksson6480 Год назад +2

    This man probably does not understand the Monty Hall problem or he would initially explained that the host does not open a random door but one of the doors that does not hide the million or the door you chose

  • @ZeroKage69
    @ZeroKage69 Год назад +2

    I like how Simon says asking the question "is my red the same as your red" is something we probably all did in childhood meanwhile here I was at like 26 while bingeing on math and science youtube videos that I finally had the thought that we could all be seeing different colors but just calling them the same names.

    • @W1LDTANG
      @W1LDTANG 10 месяцев назад

      When I was a kid, most of my friends thought I was crazy when I brought up this question... I was always happy being that dude, and now my bubble was popped 20yrs after the fact; when I find out it was just my friends that were...................... Lmao 😂🤣😂

  • @roblyndon5267
    @roblyndon5267 Год назад +6

    By the way, you explained the answer before you did the explanation. The probability of your choice being correct is 33% (ok, 33 1/3 -- let's just run wth it). Tha means that the chances of it being one of the other two is 66%. Then he shows you which one of the two it is not. But the probability of it being one of the other two (the one the host didn't show you) is still 66%.
    I knew there was a simpler explanation than all the conditional probability waffle I've read.

  • @markfinlay422
    @markfinlay422 Год назад +4

    I love the Monty Hall problem. I've won money with that as most people don't understand it.

    • @user-mj5bl5dy1b
      @user-mj5bl5dy1b 13 дней назад

      Most people think it's an even chance. They don't use logic

  • @ThereIsNoOtherHandleLikeMine
    @ThereIsNoOtherHandleLikeMine 7 дней назад

    A math professor told me I was wrong about the Monty Hall problem, and refused to discuss it.

  • @JonMartinYXD
    @JonMartinYXD Год назад +5

    The real key to understanding the Monty Hall Problem is that _the prize does not move._ Starting out, there are X doors (where X = 3 in the classic problem), each with a prize probability of 1/X. All the doors are in one group and the probability of the prize being behind a door in that group is 1. However as soon as you choose a door, you have split the doors into two groups: we will call them C (door you chose) and R (the doors you rejected). There is only one door in group C, so the probability of the prize being in C is 1/X. There are X - 1 doors in R, so the probability of the prize being in R is (X-1)/X. No matter which doors in R the host opens the probabilities of the two groups remain as they were, 1/X for C and (X-1)/X for R, because _the prize does not move._ Eventually there will be only one door left unopened in group R. What is the probability that that door hides the prize?

    • @charlesq7866
      @charlesq7866 Год назад +1

      That's a useful explanation, thanks. Maybe you can answer a follow-up question or two please?
      First question:
      Let's use Simon's 100 curtain example, but instead of the host opening curtains that they choose, a number of curtains are revealed but randomly so. The host is just there for show but doesn't actually choose anything. Does this affect the outcome?
      Second question:
      Let's say that after I pick a curtain, the host reveals 98 curtains (either randomly or selectively, I don't know if/what difference it makes), then I switch to the other curtain, as offered by the host, and then a friend of mine walks onto the stage.
      However, my friend hasn't watched the show and isn't told which curtain I originally picked and isn't told if I switched or not. He just sees 98 opened banana curtains and 2 closed curtains. Then he's told to pick one.
      Intuitively I'd say my friend has a 50/50 chance of picking correctly, but how can it be that he and I seemingly have the same choice but might have different probabilities of outcomes?
      Thanks in advance.

    • @JonMartinYXD
      @JonMartinYXD Год назад

      @@charlesq7866 1. It only changes the outcome if the prize is accidentally revealed. If the Random Curtain Opening Device opens only one curtain, and it is a banana, you should still switch to one of the other 98 closed curtains. Your probability of winning will increase from 0.01 to 0.01010204... If the RCOD opens two curtains with bananas, switching to one of the other 97 closed curtains increases your probability of winning to 0.01020619..., and so on.
      2. Your intuition is correct. If your friend walks in, has no information of what has happened ("what's with all the bananas?"), and is asked to choose a closed curtain, they have a 0.5 probability of winning. The two of you have the same choice, but you have _more information._ Your friend only knows that there are two curtains and one prize. You know that the prize was somewhere behind one of 100 curtains. When you chose your curtain you split the curtains into two groups: your one curtain, with a 1/100 probability of winning, and the other 99, each with a 1/100 probability but _collectively_ with a 99/100 probability of concealing the prize. As curtains are opened that 99/100 becomes concentrated onto fewer and fewer curtains until only one remains in the group you did not choose.
      With no information, your friend's choice is an _independent trial_ and I think this is where a lot of people get tripped up by this problem. They think that your second choice, to stick or switch, is an independent trial when it is not. For it to be an independent trial for you, you would have to lose the information you had already been given. The only way that could be done is if after the reveal of all the bananas the prize was somehow randomly redistributed between the two remaining closed curtains.
      Here is another example of the problem, a simple card game with a standard deck of cards. The goal is to get the ace of spades, if you have it when all the cards have been turned over, you win some money. The deck is shuffled and spread out face down. You are asked to pick a card, any card. The card you pick is placed just aside, still face down, you do not get to look at it. Then the dealer flips over the remaining cards, one at a time for dramatic effect. If it isn't the ace of spades the card is tossed in a garbage can under the dealer's table. The dealer gets through all the cards until just two remain: your card, and the dealer's last card. Let's now consider three scenarios. In the first scenario, you are given the option to stick with your card or switch to the dealer's last card. You know now that the correct choice is to switch: your card has a 1/52 probability of being the ace of spades, the dealer's card has a 51/52 probability. In the second scenario your friend walks up to join the game. They have no idea what has happened so far - not even which card is "yours" - they just know the goal is to find the ace of spades and that one of the two cards on the table is it. From their perspective, with the information they have, the probabilities are equal. In the third scenario, instead of your friend coming by, the dealer shuffles the last two cards (in such a way that you cannot tell which is which), places them back on the table, then asks you if you want to stick with "your" card, or switch. Your card isn't really "your" card anymore, is it? The prize has been randomly redistributed. You have lost all the information you had. Your choice has become an independent trial. Now you are just like your friend: the probabilities of either card being the ace of spades are equal.

    • @khemkaslehrling3840
      @khemkaslehrling3840 Год назад

      @@charlesq7866 YES. Exactly. Most explanations of the MHP assert that somehow when an option is eliminated from a set (a door opened in this case) that its initial "share" of probability is passed only to some sub groups and not the others. This is arbitrary and problematic. If this is the case, I want to include MY door in the group with the opened door, and have MY door receive special treatment.

    • @charlesq7866
      @charlesq7866 Год назад +1

      @@JonMartinYXD Thankk you very much. I think I understand the concept better now :). Took me an hour or so in bed pondering it and varying the thought experiments, but I think I got it!

    • @charlesq7866
      @charlesq7866 Год назад

      @@khemkaslehrling3840 The reason that your door doesn't get special treatment is that when you make your initial choice you've split the groups of doors into two groups: the one you chose and the ones you rejected.
      If something happens to one of the doors in the rejected group (like the door being opened) then that affects the rejected group, not the one you chose, which is why the "success probability" (SP) of your chosen door doesn't change from its initial position.
      However, in a way, your door is included: if (as discussed in my reply to Jon Martin) you have a friend who walks in after the door in the rejected group is opened, and they don't know which door you chose, and they see the opened door and understand the game concept, then they'll know that the door opening has just now changed the SP on all the doors (for them but not for you), meaning your door is receiving the treatment of a change of SP, which you wanted.
      It might help to know that your advantage in information over your friend still puts you in a better position.
      Let's say there are 10 doors. You picked one. The SP of the right door being in your chosen group (a group of one) is 1/10=0.10, and 9/10=0.90 for the rejected group.
      A door in the rejected group is then opened, meaning the SP of the 8 remaining closed doors in the rejected group is now 0.90/8=0.1125
      Your friend then walks in and just sees 9 closed doors, 1 open door, and doesn't know which door you chose. They ignore the open door, so their SP is 1/9=0.1111111111 and this is less than your SP.

  • @paulbarnett227
    @paulbarnett227 Год назад +10

    Actually Relativity IS important to your drive to work if you use satellite navigation. The operators of GPS have to take Special and General Relativity into account for it to remain accurate otherwise it would drift because of time dilation.

  • @CZPanthyr
    @CZPanthyr Год назад +12

    This video showed me that it's okay that I never did well in maths, since it doesn't matter much in the day to day of my life.

    • @rodchallis8031
      @rodchallis8031 Год назад +4

      Astonishingly, for every day life most of us probably learn all the math we're ever going to need by about grade 3 or 4. (Or, college in Florida) Throw in a bit of percentages and knowing how to average that comes in handy sometimes, and in some backwards countries fractions which I think are taught a little later, and that's about it. Which is not to say learning beyond add subtract multiply and divide is a waste of time. Depending on what you end up doing, you may need algebra or geometry or calculus, but the vast majority of us don't. Where we bump into it in day to day life, it's done for us.

  • @aaronseet2738
    @aaronseet2738 Год назад +1

    When i first learnt the Monty Hall problem, i had to write a software program to statistically prove to my colleagues (we're IT industry) that choosing the second door is indeed 66.7% likely to have the prize.

    • @uncopino
      @uncopino Год назад

      montecarlo simulation. nice

  • @fredericb.3910
    @fredericb.3910 12 дней назад +1

    For the monty hall problem. Just put it that way : you only loose with the 'change door strategy' when your original choice was correct (1/3). So you win in other cases (2/3)

    • @jeffjo8732
      @jeffjo8732 11 дней назад

      On a similar game show, there are four doors. Each hides a pair of siblings; one has two boys, and one has two girls. The other two have one boy and one girl; one where the boy is older, and one where the girl is older. You win if you pick a door with only a single gender.
      You pick a door, and the host opens another that has two girls. So you know that your door has at least one boy, but what is the probability that it has two?
      By your logic here, "your original choice" was correct with either a 1/4 probability or a 1/2 probability. It's ambiguous, because "your original choice" could mean a winning door, or a door with two boys. But neither matches the popular answer to the equivalent "boy or girl" paradox problem, 1/3.
      Discuss.

    • @Araqius
      @Araqius 11 дней назад

      @@jeffjo8732
      In your game, the host reveal one of the winner doors.
      Let's say the host reveal all the doors, what's your winning chance?
      It's 50%, right?
      What is the difference if the host reveal one door?
      Also, the host can clearly see the result even before he open any door.

    • @jeffjo8732
      @jeffjo8732 11 дней назад

      @@Araqius "In your game, the host reveal one of the winner doors."
      But he can't reveal all of the winning doors. The way I stated it is how we make it identical to the Boy or Girl problem since in it you are told "there is at least one..." I could have made winning be choosing a mixed door, but while the principles are the same the situations change.
      And my point is that, while your answer is right with a necessary assumption, the reason you give is wrong.
      In the Monty Hall Problem, here are the possible ways the game can progress after you pick door #1:
      A) Probability 1/3: The car is behind door #3, and the host must open door #2.
      B) Probability 1/3: The car is behind door #2, and the host must open door #3.
      C) Probability 1/3: The car is behind door #1, and the host can open either #2 or #3.
      The problem is that WE DON'T KNOW HOW HE CHOOSES. But if we assume he opens door #3 with probability Q, case C separates into:
      C1) Probability Q/3: The car is behind door #1, and the host chooses to open #3.
      C2) Probability (1-Q)/3: The car is behind door #1, and the host chooses to open #2
      So, if you see him open #3, the probability that the car is behind #1 is (Q/3)/[(1/3)+(Q/3)], or Q/(1+Q). And the probability that it is behind #2 is (1/3)/[(1/3)+(Q/3)], or 1/(1+Q).
      Now, if we don't know how he chooses, we can only assume that Q=1/2, and so these become 1/3 and 2/3, as you said. But the point is that this isn't because #1 started out at 1/3. It has to be re-calculated, and can be anything between 0 and 1/2

    • @Araqius
      @Araqius 11 дней назад

      @@jeffjo8732
      The host can clearly see the result even before he open any door.
      If he see you pick BB, he know you will win.
      If he see you pick GG, he know you will win.
      Unless he do something like revealing the door with GB and BG.

    • @fredericb.3910
      @fredericb.3910 11 дней назад

      So the host opens a single gender door (a WINNING one), which is different from the Monty Hall where the host opens a LOOSING one.
      Anyway. In this case, I would definitely choose the winning door because it is winning. Remember the strategy is to win (obviously) and I am shown a door which leads to win so I take it (1/1) and in this case it is possible.
      So the host always shows a wrong one (otherwise the game ends with the succes of the participant)
      Bsed on this premises let's go further.
      So half of the time if I pick well first (two boys or two girls (2/4) -> (1/2)), I am expecting the host to show me a loosing door ( not a winning, otherwise I win)
      So let me rephrase it.
      A game with 4 doors : (M/M) (M/F) (F/M) (F/F)
      Participant chooses one of the four.
      The host show the participant one doors :
      option 1) Host show a winning one (1/4) : we already ruled it out, otherwise the game is stupid and always won by the participant.
      option 2) Host show a loosing one (2/4) (more interesting) and in this case, the participant is shown a wrong door and he originally choosed a door which is (1/2) chance to win.
      So two cases for option 2 where a wrong door is showned :
      a) original choice is right (1/2):
      changing -> one the two remaining door one is right and the other not (1/2)
      not changing -> Participant stays with (1/2) chances
      b) original choice is wrong (1/2):
      changing -> definitely good because Participant original choice was bad and he is shown a bad one, so if he changes he wins
      not changing -> definitely bad because Participant original choice was bad and he stays with his choice

      and because changing does not affects a) but affects b) in a good way, CHANGING strategy seems to be the better


      what are the odds now
      a) 1/2 whatever you do one half of the time
      b) 1/1 if you change the other half
      so : 1/2 * (1 / 2) + 1/2 * (1) => 3/4
      You may wander why the solution to Monty Hall which is (2/3 best strategy) is more little than /4 best stategy for your problem)
      It is because there are more good solutions proportionaly (2 on 4 in this case) than in the Monty Hall (1 on 3)
      This raised two questions which I found interesting.
      How to explain... I took a lot of words to try to explain it. How can I decrease the number of words to explain it (and in a better way).
      The actual challenge is here to explain. As I review the above lines, I am not pleased. Please help me to improve my explanation.
      First on the Monty Hall problem
      Second on this 2 kids and four doors problem.
      And I would say, this hundred curtain problem presented in the video which leads to more perplexity...
      It's says that 98 (or 99 if you originally picked the right one) curtains are shown with bananas behind than it is obvious for you to change.
      Ok, nice way to pull you in the right direction but definitely drag you in the wrong direction.
      What if, (with the same problem , "hundred curtains") I only showed you, as a host, a curtain ( on the hundred which are present) which contains bananas,
      would you think it is worth to change or to stay.
      And Thank you to say 'discuss' in your post. It is rarer and rarer to read this.

  • @theawesomeman9821
    @theawesomeman9821 Год назад +58

    As my former calculus teacher once said, "Math isn't complicated, it's just beyond the comprehension of simpletons."

    • @josepherhardt164
      @josepherhardt164 Год назад +6

      Ouch.

    • @onebylandtwoifbysearunifby5475
      @onebylandtwoifbysearunifby5475 Год назад +11

      Doesn't sound like your calculus teacher was in any danger of getting a Fields medal.

    • @nidurnevets
      @nidurnevets Год назад +8

      The great Feynman, who was gifted in math, admitted that when it came to music he couldn't carry a tune. My father, born about the same year as Feynman, was a violinist in a major symphony. He could carry a tune. So, not all of us have the same abilities.

    • @kens97sto171
      @kens97sto171 Год назад +10

      That is a ridiculous and poor way to teach or incentivize anyone.
      If your calculus teacher could not rebuild an car engine or write a symphony... is he a simpleton??
      Different types of smarts.. All of which are important.

    • @ZiplineToCompleteIgnorance
      @ZiplineToCompleteIgnorance Год назад +4

      George Bernard Shaw said ‘Those who can, do; those who can’t, teach.’

  • @TheEulerID
    @TheEulerID Год назад +4

    The Monty Hall problem (and this one is a considerable variation from the original - where are the goats) is, as is often the case, inadequately described. Once extremely important point is the the host must always open one of the other two curtains. It is not a matter of deciding to do it on the day, but they have to do it each and every time and, what's more, you have to know they are going to do it. Otherwise the host might be doing it selectively to mislead you. Also, of course, the host must know where each prize is, and they must never open either the competitor's original curtain or the winning curtain.
    Once all the conditions are clearly explained then it's simple; you change your decision and you double the chance of winning the prize from 1 in 3 to 2 in three.
    It is, incidentally, not a mathematical discovery at all. It's a bit of basic probability theory, just with a (usually) incompletely explained scenario.

    • @khemkaslehrling3840
      @khemkaslehrling3840 Год назад

      Try modeling all the scenarios. Imagine a game with 3 doors, and 1 car and 2 goats.
      Assume the contestant chooses door 1. There are now 4 scenarios and two options each, resulting in eight outcomes. And the split of win/lose for stay/switch is 50/50.
      1. Car / Goat / Goat - host shows you door 2 - switch lose / stay win
      2. Car / Goat / Goat - host shows you door 3 - switch lose / stay win
      3. Goat / Car / Goat - host shows you door 3 - switch win / stay lose
      4. Goat / Goat / Car - host shows you door 2 - switch win / stay lose

    • @TheEulerID
      @TheEulerID Год назад +1

      @@khemkaslehrling3840 I know perfectly well the scenarios, and worked all this out long ago and even tested my mathematics with a simulation, just to make sure.
      However, the point you completely miss is that the Monty Hall problem is often not fully specified. The extra conditions are
      a) the host must know what is behind each door
      b) the host must only open another door with the lesser prize
      c) most importantly of all, the host must do this every single time
      Without (a) & (b) we are in a different scenario as either could lead to the main prize being revealed.
      If (c) is not met, then the host might only decide to open another door when the competitor has already picked the main prize. Of they might only do so if the competitor chose a lesser prize, or maybe some mixture of the two. The host might act to help, or to hinder.
      Like many probabilistic problems, it's essential to be very precise or it is easy to be lead astray.

    • @barryschwarz
      @barryschwarz 16 дней назад

      @@TheEulerID I am forever mystified that people hear the words "game show" and do not immediately understand that the host will never reveal the prize. Thus, the game show host must know what is behind the doors. And with this it is inferred thhat the host always never reveals the prize.
      Perhaps some people really don't understand how game shows work?

  • @kevinduke8928
    @kevinduke8928 Год назад +2

    On the first issue (Monty Hall) you could not do this at home by yourself. The hidden variable here goes beyond math. That is why the confusion. You need another person that knows the answers. He/she will reveal one of the remaining doors/cards that is NOT the main prize. He/she knows which door/card is correct. By eliminating one wrong answer, the probabilities change. To this this accurately though, requires someone knowing in advance and knowing what to reveal and what not to reveal.
    It also should be mentioned that it worked so well on the show because most people stick with their original decision for psychological reasons. Assuming it’s always the same odds, they would rather be wrong by staying with what they chose then by switching and finding out that they would have been right if they didn’t switch. Of course they assume the host is unaware of the correct answer too. They are oblivious that the host is showing them a particular door for a reason.

    • @klaus7443
      @klaus7443 Год назад +2

      You can take three cards, two marked 'Goat/switching wins', one marked 'Car/staying wins', and simply write down what you first picked.

  • @druid62
    @druid62 Год назад +1

    The way that the initial story is presented, isn't clear: it is mentioned that the host opens curtain "3", after the candidate selected "1" , but does that mean that he opens (from "2 or 3") the one that doesn't have the prize behind it, or that the host always opens "3" if the candidate selects a prize-less"1", or etc. etc.

    • @morbideddie
      @morbideddie Год назад +1

      Yeah, it’s not very well explained here. The Monty Hall Problem relies on the host always revealing from the other two curtains and never revealing the grand prize.

  • @Jacovie
    @Jacovie Год назад +3

    My cognitive dissonance isn’t allowing me to accept some of this 😔

  • @secheltfishmarket6419
    @secheltfishmarket6419 Год назад +3

    The Monty Hall Problem is based on the choice that the participant could of had, not on the new choice that the participant now has. If the player is shown one of the curtains and now has to sit down and a new player from back stage with no knowledge of the first players choice now stands in to pick from the two curtains... that new player has a 50/50 chance.

    • @twotubefamily9323
      @twotubefamily9323 Год назад

      Nope - try again

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад +1

      The new player chooses with a 50/50 chance of what he'll choose. However, if he selects the first curtain (preselected by the previous player), he will still get only 1/3 chance of the million; and if he picks the other, 2/3!
      Heh heh!

    • @kegginstructure
      @kegginstructure 26 дней назад

      @@twotubefamily9323 Actually, secheltfishmarket6419 is correct. In isolation, a 2nd player who doesn't know about which door had been picked really DOES have 50-50 odds. Seriously. Because there are TWO problems operating simultaneously in the true Monty Hall problem. The 3-door game (where a zonk has been identified) retains the 1/3 and 2/3 odds. The 2-door game, however, does not have the same odds. There, it really is 50-50 - but you get fooled because you only see the second choice and (incorrectly) put aside the fact of a first pick.

  • @aidarosullivan5269
    @aidarosullivan5269 Год назад +1

    When I showed Monty Hall problem on my Probability class, professor was flabbergasted because she didn't heard about it before, and didn't believe until she run the number herself.

  • @ZlothZloth
    @ZlothZloth Год назад +2

    Seems like there's a little more to the Monty Hall - he also doesn't want to show the banana. If he reveals that, you're going to win. Maybe you'll win 1K, maybe 1M, but there's no chance of coming away with a banana that's been under studio lights for too long, which means the choice isn't going to be as entertaining. If you pick the $1M curtain, he'll show the $1K choice. Same if you pick the banana curtain. However, if you pick the $1K curtain, he's going to be forced to show the banana. So, if he shows you the banana, you switch and get the $1M for sure!

  • @ravenlord4
    @ravenlord4 11 месяцев назад +7

    What helps with the Monty Hall problem is that while your choice is random, Monty's in NOT random. When you pick, you have a 1 in 3 chance of picking the prize door. When Monty opens a door, he has a 0 in 3 chance of picking the prize door. Therefor the remaining door has the remaining 2 in 3 chance of being the prize. :)

    • @lrvogt1257
      @lrvogt1257 6 месяцев назад

      It doesn't matter what you pick initially because it's ignored and a new scenario is presented. The host's reveal is never random. It must and will always be a goat or the game is ruined. The player always and only makes a real choice between one of two options, a car and a goat.

    • @ravenlord4
      @ravenlord4 6 месяцев назад +3

      @@lrvogt1257 That's not true. Try the scenario with 100 doors. Your first pick is 1% chance of success. Then Monty opens 98 doors with goats. Now there are two doors left, Your door (1%) and Monty's door (99%). It is NOT 50-50 ;)

    • @scottparker1741
      @scottparker1741 26 дней назад

      Hmm I don’t think you understand the Monty problem

  • @pamelamays4186
    @pamelamays4186 Год назад +7

    On my first day of second year algebra in the tenth grade, my math teacher drew a 4 on the blackboard, then said, "See this four? It's not real."
    My fifteen year old brain was blown.🤯

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg Год назад +4

      The confusion comes in when forget that all of math comes down to counting. It's just that what is being counted has become more and more complex. The symbol "4" isn't real, but is used to mark that "there are 4 things". "1/4" means "1 thing out of 4 things", "4/2" is "4 things separated into 2 groups", and so on. The numbers themselves are not real, they're just labels for convenience that represent what IS real.

    • @konroh2
      @konroh2 9 дней назад

      @@Vaeldarg Symbols are actually real, they represent real things. When we say they aren't real we mean they aren't concrete, but right now I'm writing letters that convey to your mind real things.

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg 9 дней назад

      @@konroh2 Where were you going with this?

    • @konroh2
      @konroh2 9 дней назад

      @@Vaeldarg Concepts are real things, so language and symbols are real. An idea of something is real. Real things aren't just material, what is invisible is also real. When someone says maths isn't real because it's just a symbol it's denying the spiritual reality of ideas, which are also real.

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg 9 дней назад

      @@konroh2 "the spiritual reality of ideas" is easy to deny, because no it isn't real.

  • @sovincine8279
    @sovincine8279 Год назад +1

    The easier explanation for the Monte Hall problem isn't to say the probability changes. Because it doesn't for the purposes of understanding. When you have 3 options, no matter what you choose you have a 66% chance of being wrong. That doesn't change.

    •  20 дней назад +1

      True, for the original Monty Hall problem.
      But not the case for the experiment shown in the video clip. There are three unique prizes. Revealing the middle prize behind a door actually changes what we know about the door we first selected. It means this door can't have the middle prize. At this point, the chance we selected the grand prize is now 50%, up from 33%.

  • @bobpourri9647
    @bobpourri9647 Год назад +1

    The secret to understanding the Monty Hall problem is one needs to get over the notion that it is a pure probabilities exercise: Human intellect intervenes and skews the results. IF Monty did not know what lie behind the curtains and picked the curtain to reveal at random, THEN pure probabilities would take over.

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      Eh, no!
      When you pick the first curtain, it has 1/3 chance of being correct.
      Meanwhile...
      *The other two curtains together* have 2/3 chance of holding the jackpot.
      The host removing one non-jackpot curtain of these two is just a detail - that 'side of the equation' is still 2/3 .

    • @bobpourri9647
      @bobpourri9647 Год назад

      @@Michael_Arnold I assume that - in a game driven only by chance - if Monty happened to reveal the jackpot , which would then be out of the mix, the game would be pretty much ruined: The chance of winning would go to zero no matter what the contestant did. On the other hand, if Monty randomly and unknowingly selected a curtain that contains a booby-prize, then the remaining curtains each would retain their 1/3 chance of being the jackpot......even odds to win with either one. But it is NEVER the case that the jackpot is revealed prematurely. Human intervention.

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      @bobpourri9647 Well, if the host reveals the $1M, there's no game, really. But that's all irrelevant to the mathematical probabilities involved, though. It doesn't matter whether your goal is to win the $1M or the bananas, your *chances* of doing so double if you change, *provided the host reveals an unwanted prize, either before or after you change.*
      Here are the three possibilities of what lies behind the doors:
      0 0 $
      or
      0 $ 0
      or
      $ 0 0
      (where $ is a coveted prize, and 0 is unwanted).
      If you select the first choice each time, and eliminate a 0 from what remains,
      sticking to your choice gives you a win 1/3 times.
      Changing your choice gives you a win 2/3 times.
      *As long as the host reveals a dud prize,* the odds tilt to 2/3 for a change of choice - mathematically and forever! ; )

  • @dank2476
    @dank2476 Год назад +3

    By choosing the other curtain does not mean you surely will win the million, it's just that the probability is higher. Maybe your 1st choice could already be the winner.

  • @blaster-zy7xx
    @blaster-zy7xx Год назад +5

    The part that Simon leaves out of the puzzle that needs to be given to make the game work is that Monty will always open a curtain that does NOT reveal the million dollars.

    • @twotubefamily9323
      @twotubefamily9323 Год назад

      I'm guessing math is tricky for you

    • @blaster-zy7xx
      @blaster-zy7xx Год назад +2

      ​@@twotubefamily9323 No, I have a science degree and went all through calculus. The point is that the "chances" are calculated by telling us that after selecting a door and one of the other doors is exposed, should we change our selection to the other door? BUT there is nothing in this set of "rules" that says the second door MIGHT expose the million dollars, and nothing in the rules that we cannot select the opened door showing the million dollars. THAT change the odds dramatically. But we ASSUME the rules are that the million dollars cannot be exposed at the second door opening and that we can't select the open door.

    • @sverkeren
      @sverkeren Год назад +3

      @@twotubefamily9323
      blaster is correct. This is yet another sloppy/incorrect formulated Monty Hall problem. The host does not "cheekily decides" to open another door.
      In classic Monty Hall, the host opens another door knowing that it is not the big price. And he would have done this regardless which door you initially choose. THEN you will have a 2/3 chance to win if you switch.
      For example, if the host "cheekily decides" to open one of the other doors randomly, discovers it to not be the price and therefore offer you to switch. THEN you will still have 50/50 chance between the two remaining doors.

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      @sverkeren Respectfully, no!
      When you pick the first curtain, it has 1/3 chance of being correct.
      Meanwhile...
      *The other two curtains together* have 2/3 chance of holding the jackpot.
      The host removing the non-jackpot curtain of these two is just a detail - that 'side of the equation' is still 2/3 .

    • @sverkeren
      @sverkeren Год назад +1

      @@Michael_Arnold Respectfully, yes!
      In classic Monty Hall, if you first choose wrong (with 2/3 chance), then the host will practically show you where the price is by AVOIDING that door.
      If the host does not actively avoid the winning door, then you don't get that probability boost. Instead that probability get evenly distributed on the remaining doors. What could have happened matters.

  • @Brian_1597_of_Nazareth
    @Brian_1597_of_Nazareth Год назад +1

    What makes the "change" choice more easy understandable to be the better one, is often not mentioned: the quiz master adds information. Because usually he never will open the jackpot in the intermediate round - he knows where it is. If he'd randomly open curtains, one out of three times the game would be over before you are asked a second time. That's exactly what you have to have in mind: the quiz master tells by ALWAYS showing one lower choice. Or the other way round: being in the second round of the same game is different to a random mix of constellations behind the curtain prior to every new choice. If the game was like that, if after the first opening the remaining two would be shuffled before your second choice, a fifty-fifty chance would be newly created.

  • @diegomartinez7180
    @diegomartinez7180 26 дней назад

    My economics teacher explained Nash Equilibrium to me like this: Imagine there are two prisoners about to be tried. The detectives have been able to find out that at least one of them (or both) was the culprit of a crime but they don't know who actually did it. Because of that, they only have both of them as accessories. So, here it is... The police starts questioning both prisoners separately. If both of them can provide testimony on the other, both of them will spend 7 years in jail as culprits who helped in the investigation (a sum of 14 years). If none of them speak, they will both spend less than a year in jail as accessories (a sum of under 2 years), but if only one of them rats the other one out, he will be let free as innocent and the other one will spend 10 years in jail as the sole culprit (a sum of 10 years).
    In the end, the "natural equilibrium" will be that, on the fear of being accused by the other one, and in the hope to be let free, they will both speak and they will both spend 7 years in prison, the worst possible outcome for both prisoners (14 years in total).
    The possibility of any of them not speaking while the other one speaks is very remote, so this one is not an equilibrium, it is very unlikely, it shouldn't happen, if they knew about "game theory", they will realize the option of being let go while the other one stays in prison is pretty much impossible.
    But there is another equilibrium. The one where both of them gain the most. If they both stay silent, if they can agree not to say anything, they will both actually spend very little time in prison and the penalty is the smallest (less than 2 years in sum). This is called "Nash Equilibrium", but for it to happen, they need to agree to do it and trust each other. If any of the two suspects the other one might end up blabbing, they will both turn on each other and spend a sum of 14 years in jail. So this equilibrium is very, very fragile.
    Now bring that to your example of the atomic bombs and it is easier to understand. If country 1 strikes first, and country 2 does not retaliate, country 2 will be destroyed, along with everything nearby, and country 1will end up as the global superpower (this is the unlikely, non-equilibrium option where half the world is destroyed anyway). If country 1 strikes first and country 2 retaliates, then they will both be destroyed (along with the whole world), which is the worst possible outcome but actually the "natural equilibrium", the most likely one to happen. Unless they speak with each other and agree not to attack but only to retaliate, in which case both of them will never attack, the best outcome possible, which is the "Nash equilibrium", a very fragile situation, but our current state of affairs.

  • @bishoukun
    @bishoukun Год назад +3

    6:10 The prisoner's dilemma! I can see where it doesn't match up perfectly, but influencing the outcome of the other with the decision of one when both must decide, that part lines up. The first one I knew because of VSauce2 - Kevin does a great job at explaining the brain-melting probability math with /more math/ except it works well. Y'all did a good job here with these, especially making the point that the game show host is the factor that changes the probability.

  • @dcsteve7869
    @dcsteve7869 Год назад +6

    Simon: let me show you two mathematical ways you may be wrong about the world and how to better understand it.
    also Simon: Hehe just kidding, it's all a lie
    thanks Simon for destroying my mathematically perfect world today.

  • @palemale2501
    @palemale2501 Год назад +1

    Monty Hall puzzle - as a logical engineer I thought I had proved in my head, after a hour or so and 2 different ways, that there was no advantage to swop my first choice.
    Only when I tried it (by myself) using 3 playing cards, and after only 3 hands did I realise the logic - yes swop your first choice - so 2 out of 3 hands you will win the big prize (but only 1 in 3 hands if you stick).

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      Yes, I tried that too.
      When you pick the first curtain, it has 1/3 chance of being correct.
      Meanwhile...
      *The other two curtains together* have 2/3 chance of holding the jackpot.
      The host removing one non-jackpot curtain of these two is just a cosmetic detail - that 'side of the equation' is still 2/3 .

  • @erichbaumeister4648
    @erichbaumeister4648 Год назад +20

    A help for the Monty Hall problem: 1) Regardless of which curtain you initially select, the probability that the million bucks is behind one or the other curtain is ⅔. 2) No matter which curtain you initially select, Monty can _always_ open one of the other two curtains, showing you a worthless item behind it because he knows where the big money is. 3) When he opens one of the other curtains, he shifts the entire ⅔ probability from two curtains to the one other curtain he didn't open. 4) After he opens one curtain you have the choice of two curtains: your original choice (⅓ probability) and the one other curtain Monty didn't open (⅔ probability).
    By changing your selection you therefore double your chance of getting rich.

    • @khemkaslehrling3840
      @khemkaslehrling3840 Год назад +3

      By what magic does the share of probability of the opened curtain transfer to only one of the other curtains, and not be split across both? Why not then just declare that the curtain you chose is grouped with the curtain the host opens, giving it "the entire probability of the opened curtain" and making your door 2/3rds? This is the fallacy of this Monty Hall thing.

    • @justblaze6802
      @justblaze6802 Год назад +5

      ​@@khemkaslehrling3840 Think of it this way; 3 items behind 3 curtains, 1 prize & 2 duds (worthless), no matter which door you choose the host can reveal a dud. Lets go through all 3 choices, Scenario #1 lets say you pick the prize curtain then the host reveals a dud curtain, if you switch you get another dud (1/3). Scenario #2 lets say you choose a dud curtain, the host can only show you the remaining dud so if you switch you pick the prize (1/3). Scenario #3 you choose the other dud, yet again the host can only choose a dud, so if you switch you pick the prize curtain (1/3). So in closing in only 1 out of 3 scenarios do you lose by switching, but if you chose to switch you'd be right 66.7% (2/3) of the time.

    • @jordandesmond5742
      @jordandesmond5742 Год назад

      ​@@justblaze6802 that explanation just gave me the light bulb moment, thank you

    • @erichbaumeister4648
      @erichbaumeister4648 Год назад

      Another help to those who aren't yet convinced: when Monty opens one door, think of it as him opening *ALL* the other doors except the one you chose and one other one.

    • @quardlepleen
      @quardlepleen Год назад +1

      ​@@khemkaslehrling3840 You choose one door out of 3. If I offer you to let you switch for the two remaining doors, would you take the deal?
      Of course you would, because your odds would be 2/3. That's what's happening here, except that the host is opening one of the two doors first.
      But you are still effectively getting to choose 2 doors by switching.

  • @gregfine
    @gregfine 4 дня назад

    Very simple. You started with 1 in 3 chance. Which means the other two choices combine to 2 in 3 chance. When the host eliminates a loser from the remaining 2, all the remaining odds (2 in 3) lie solely on the choice you did not originally pick. So you can change your odds from 1 in 3 to 2 in 3 by changing your choice.

  • @bhgtree
    @bhgtree Год назад +6

    Amazing as always, I love maths, but I don't need maths to Love Simon's videos. Thanks guys.
    👍

  • @Xanderviceory
    @Xanderviceory Год назад +4

    I cannot express how much I love and hate this at the same time. I wasn't ready for the whole maths is perfect but not real bit.

  • @Jaccayumitty
    @Jaccayumitty Год назад +2

    The Monty Hall problem only rewards changing your guess if it's assumed that the host knows where the million dollars is and will always open another curtain. If that condition isn't met, then the remaing two curtains each have s 50:50 chance of hiding the million dollars (and in one game out of every three, the million dollars will be behind the curtain the host opens, so you're choosing between the thiusand dollars and the banana, and you have a 50:50 chance of that)

  • @JonMartinYXD
    @JonMartinYXD Год назад +2

    I went down into the comments to ask what a "tritium bomb" was (it can't be a thermonuclear bomb because that doesn't match the history Simon gives it), but instead discovered so, so many people _still_ don't get the Monty Hall Problem.

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад +1

      The Real Monty Hall Problem is the number of people who just can't reason it out, even when explained simply!

  • @renaissanceredneck3695
    @renaissanceredneck3695 Год назад +4

    Hopefully he will explain why two people that speak the same language call it two separate things.
    Maths vs. Math

    • @JBaughb
      @JBaughb Год назад +2

      ooh, I can explain that. Super easy. One of them is wrong. ;)

    • @rustythecrown9317
      @rustythecrown9317 Год назад

      Math is the subject , Maths are the stuff you do in the subject. i.e. '' There are many maths to do today , lets get mathing''.

    • @kaltaron1284
      @kaltaron1284 Год назад +1

      The science is called Mathmatics. One side shortens it to Maths the other to Math. This also changed over the years which one was the more accepted one where.

  • @al1383
    @al1383 Год назад +4

    After trying to contradict your Monty Python odds, I concede. You're correct.
    You have 2/3 chance of picking the wrong door. So it's better to choose the other door.

    • @Wuddigot
      @Wuddigot 17 дней назад

      I still dont think that is true. When you are given the chance to either keep your current choice or choose another, you are actually just rechoosing based on what is still unknown. Just because they say "keep your current choice" does not mean that you are keeping your initial probability.
      Please respond, because there might be a high probability that I'm missing something :P

    • @al1383
      @al1383 17 дней назад

      @Wuddigot Simplest way to think about it.
      You know how the game works. You know that you will be shown a losing door after you choose a door.
      Beginning of the game you have a 1 in 3 chance of picking the winning door. A 2 in 3 chance of picking the wrong door.
      Would you agree 2 in 3 odds are better than 1 in 3? So you are most likely to choose a wrong door.
      So knowing how the game works, you pick your first door knowing you're more likely to pick one of the 2 out of 3 that are losers. Because of this, when a door is removed, you pick the other.
      Definitely not a fool proof way to win
      Just gives you better odds.
      You gotta look at the odds of picking the wrong door to determine the best odds of picking the correct door.

    • @al1383
      @al1383 17 дней назад

      @@Wuddigot I just reread you comment.
      Keeping the first door keeps your original 1 in 3 odds. So keeping your first choice does keep your original probability.
      Gotta bring the odds of choosing one of the wrong doors into the equation. 2 in 3, which is more likely.
      Start of game you're thinking "I have the best chance of picking a wrong door" (2 in 3)
      So after you pick a door (odds are its a loser) you know one of the other two doors are more likely to be the winning door. Right?
      Since one of them doors are removed from the game, you pick the other. Giving you 2 in 3 odds of it being the winning door.

    • @Wuddigot
      @Wuddigot 14 дней назад

      @@al1383 That just isnt true though. The odds of you choosing the wrong door is now less because there are less wrong doors that you would choose from. You will not choose a door you know is wrong, and therefor the conditions (and probability) have changed.
      Am I hearing the initial problem incorrectly or something? guy chooses door, before result is revealed he is told one of the wrong doors and given the choice to choose again... Is that it? he now still does not know which of the doors is right, but he does know that one of the two remaining doors is wrong.
      If I am not missing a detail, this is an iterative problem, as in each completion of the action loop starting at the beginning with a different set of conditions.

    • @al1383
      @al1383 14 дней назад

      @@Wuddigot you going to get me racking my brain on this again! 😃
      To tired today. I'll respond later

  • @williams.benjaminiii9043
    @williams.benjaminiii9043 22 дня назад

    Accordingly per the logic of the Monty Hall Problem, your odds of buying a winning lottery ticket go up if buy one and then tear it up, and then buy a different one instead. It's a fact that all of the losing tickets will be exposed and your odds of buying the winning ticket go up so long as you destroy the 1st lottery ticket that you purchased.

  • @roninkegawa1804
    @roninkegawa1804 19 дней назад

    Here is an easy explanation of the monthy hall problem. When you chose 1 door out of 3 you have a 33% chance of being right, and the other 2 doors together are 66%. In essence, when you change your choicer after one door is revealed, it is as if you picked the initial 2 doors you had not picked initially, hence you now have a 66% chance of winning.

  • @freakychick1978
    @freakychick1978 Год назад +5

    The only thing that confused me about the Monty Hall problem was how many decades male math inclined people tried to disprove the woman who solved it. Shout out to her and my own home state of Missouri.

    • @1217BC
      @1217BC 10 дней назад

      What's worse, she didn't solve it. This was a well established reality before she ever said anything. Marilyn vos Savant just answered the question for someone in an article in 1990. This probability problem was solved over a century earlier. Then a bunch of twits responded without actually looking into it. So, the same phenomenon as social media comments. Give a large enough sample of humanity a forum, and you'll get a lot of very stupid responses. Those who already understand likely won't comment, those who learn only might comment, but those who hold close their ignorance will shout from the rooftops.

  • @lostbutfreesoul
    @lostbutfreesoul Год назад +4

    The way I rational the Monty Hall problem is this:
    The first probability is still collapsing...
    If you don't modify your choice, the original 1/3 probability continues to collapse like normal...
    If you do modify your choice you are really getting 2 doors instead of 1... one picked by the host, and one by you.

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад +1

      You still get the same odds. All doors are 1/3. So the host reveals one... you still have 50% chance with the remaining doors. You gain nothing in terms of odds, you only get to see what was behind one door that you did not choose anyway. There's no 66% chance in this scenario, ever.

    • @JonMartinYXD
      @JonMartinYXD Год назад

      @@lgmediapcsalon9440 No. The key to understanding the problem is that _the prize does not move._ Starting out, there are X doors (where X = 3 in the classic problem), each with a prize probability of 1/X. All the doors are in one group and the probability of the prize being behind a door in that group is 1. However as soon as you choose a door, you have split the doors into two groups: we will call them C (door you chose) and R (the doors you rejected). There is only one door in group C, so the probability of the prize being in C is 1/X. There are X - 1 doors in R, so the probability of the prize being in R is (X - 1)/X. No matter which doors in R the host opens the probabilities of the two groups remain as they were, 1/X for C and (X-1)/X for R, because _the prize does not move._ Eventually there will be only one door left unopened in group R. What is the probability that that door hides the prize?

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад

      @@JonMartinYXD Where did I write that the prizes move? If there's 3 doors and one is open, the chance is 1/2.

    • @JonMartinYXD
      @JonMartinYXD Год назад

      @@lgmediapcsalon9440 The only way the odds can "reset" is if the prize can move after Monty opens a door.
      Let's put it another way. What if before Monty asked you to choose a door, he asked you if you would like to choose one door or two doors? You'd be crazy to restrict yourself to just one door, right? Choosing one door gives you a 1/3 chance of winning, choosing two gives you a 2/3 chance of winning. Well that is exactly what Monty is offering you after he opens a door.
      Three doors: A, B, and C. From your perspective, A has a 1/3 chance of hiding the prize, B has a 1/3 chance of hiding the prize, and C has a 1/3 chance of hiding the prize. You choose door A. You have a 1/3 chance of winning. Monty opens door B or C to reveal a goat (the goat is not the prize). Monty now offers you the chance to stick or switch. This is equivalent to you previously being given the option of choosing door A or choosing _both B and C._ Since you are the one determining if the choice is between A or B+C, B or A+C, and C or A+B, and since the prize is already in place, Monty cannot change the probabilities. If you choose only one door you have a 1/3 chance of winning. If you choose two doors, by switching, you have a 2/3 chance of winning.

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад

      @@JonMartinYXD You're moving the goal post with your "pick 2 doors". Monty opens one door, two remain. You have 50% chance of winning. End of story.

  • @vendigrothianv2997
    @vendigrothianv2997 Год назад +1

    I believe that in the original Monty Hall problem player is faced with one prize (let's say million dollars) and two equally worthless duds(bananas). Also allegedly the host himself (or his assistant) knows where's what. Now assuming that there's a million dollars (A), a thousand dollars (B) and a banana (C) then if the whole probabilities would most probably change. In such a case the host would most likely want to leave the million vs. the banana in the end for the most dramatic effect. That changes everything. Looking at different scenarios: Scenario 1: player initially chooses A, and Host is left with B and C. The probability of host choosing B over C could vary from 50/50 (indifferent) to always choosing B. Scenario 2: player chooses B and the host is forced to reveal C. Scenario 3: player chooses C and the host is forced to reveal B. All three scenarios are equally 1/3 possible. Working down from the information the player has it is not difficult to calculate that the probability of the player initially choosing a million after a thousand dollar reveal would increase from the original 1/3 vs 2/3 to the 50/50 as the host becomes more likely to increase the drama, and would decrease from 1/3 to 0 accordingly in case the banana is revealed.

  • @jacemandt
    @jacemandt 16 дней назад

    The best way I've found to think of the Monte Hall problem is to make the question a little different from "What are the probabilities?"
    Imagine instead that person A *always* switches curtains and person B *always* keeps the same one. Person B will win if they picked the right curtain the first time, and person A will win if they picked the *wrong* curtain the first time (since they'll definitely switch to the right one). Who would you rather be?
    This ends up matching the probabilities explained in the video: person A picks the wrong curtain at first about 2/3 of the time, and will thus win after switching on those 2/3 of the games. Person B picks the right curtain at first about 1/3 of the time, and will thus win without switching those 1/3 of the games.

  • @laughingoutloud5742
    @laughingoutloud5742 Год назад +3

    Thank you so much for this SP episode! It's been frustrating trying to get my friends to understand this, and I've been told many times I'm high lol. Now I can send them this video and hopefully they'll finally get it 😄

  • @davidioanhedges
    @davidioanhedges Год назад +3

    The Monty Hall problem, people assume that they have no new information so it's 50/50 - but the host will *never* open the curtain with a million - so you do have new information
    The door they deliberately didn't open is more likely than the one you chose
    Even wrong maths still works ... Most spacecraft flight paths are calculated using Newtonian mathematics, and they get there just fine, only a few need to allow for the fact that it's wrong - e.g flights to Mercury ...

    • @lgmediapcsalon9440
      @lgmediapcsalon9440 Год назад

      What makes it that your initial choice ISN'T the million dollars? Nothing. The odds don't change.

    • @davidioanhedges
      @davidioanhedges 6 месяцев назад

      @@lgmediapcsalon9440 Which is why you still have 1/3 chance you were right ...
      The new information means that the 1/3 and 1/3 for the other two options merge, but your option does not change

    • @user-gy4yq8om3e
      @user-gy4yq8om3e 20 дней назад

      There is NO new information provided by opening one of the unchosen doors - at least no useful information. (Using the car/goats/doors format):-
      You knew that there was at least one goat behind the other two doors, and you knew that Monty would show you a door with a goat.
      The reveal tells you nothing useful, only that the revealed door was a door that had a goat behind it. Knowing that does not help you decide.
      If there was no reveal, and you were offered both the other two doors over your first choice, you would swap - and you would know that you are getting at least one goat.

    • @davidioanhedges
      @davidioanhedges 18 дней назад

      @@user-gy4yq8om3e The new information is that the host will not open a door to the prize so his options are limited and so you gain new information

  • @nidurnevets
    @nidurnevets Год назад +2

    In the Monty Hall Problem it finally made sense to me when I asked "when is the only time when I will not win the money?" It is when my first choice is correct, but I change to the other possible choice when asked if I want to change. Otherwise I will always win the money I think I may have seen this idea on a video by Kahn academy when they tackled this problem

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      When you pick the first curtain, it has 1/3 chance of being correct.
      Meanwhile...
      *The other two curtains together* have 2/3 chance of holding the jackpot.
      The host removing one non-jackpot curtain of these two is just a detail - that 'side of the equation' is still 2/3 .

  • @Dark_Jaguar
    @Dark_Jaguar Год назад +1

    Calling the overall concept of math "maths" is as weird sounding to my US brain as calling the force of gravity "gravities" would be.

  • @tomfoolery3847
    @tomfoolery3847 Год назад +3

    The "maths isn't real" thing reminds me of something I always thought about while learning about maths in school. We are taught, for example, to calculate the exact volume of something that's called a "perfect cube" (or take some other geometric figure). The thing I wondered about though was if there even is a thing like a perfect cube in the real world. Even the slightest imperfection on some micologic scale would the cube (or whatever figure) cause to be imperfect. If we haven't even the possibilty to measure something in the smallest possible scale, we can't assume that it's perfect.

    • @bramvanduijn8086
      @bramvanduijn8086 Год назад +2

      You might enjoy looking into the Theory Of Forms by Plato.

    • @tomfoolery3847
      @tomfoolery3847 Год назад +1

      @@bramvanduijn8086 Thanks for the tip. I might give it a try, but I don't think I'm qualified enough to understand things like this. What I just described were just the thoughts of some kid about things he learned in school.

    • @cigmorfil4101
      @cigmorfil4101 15 дней назад

      The Earth is much-much smoother than, say, a billiard ball - blown up to the same scale, the pits and bumps on a billiard ball would be much larger than the mountains and sea depths of the earth...

  • @Sakhmeth
    @Sakhmeth Год назад +7

    Another way to consider the Monty Hall problem is not to think you have a 1/3 chance of getting it right on your first guess, but that you have a 2/3 chance of getting it WRONG. So the 2/3 chance of getting it right is now with the other two doors, initially split between them. And by removing one of those doors from the equation, that 2/3 correct chance is now with the remaining door.

    • @klaus7443
      @klaus7443 Год назад

      That is not correct. You would have a 2/3 chance of picking a wrong door regardless as to the host's knowledge. In that case if he opened one of his two doors that reveals a non-prize there would be no advantage in switching.

    • @rsalehi6568
      @rsalehi6568 Год назад

      That is an explanation that makes straightforward sense.

    • @williamdoherty7824
      @williamdoherty7824 Год назад

      But by removing one door and making that door 100% wrong then it is a 50/50 it may be one of the remaining doors. 6ou can come u0 with some pseudo intellectual nonsense explaining how the myths shows that no to be true but in real world application its 50/50 not 66/33

    • @rsalehi6568
      @rsalehi6568 Год назад

      @@williamdoherty7824 Create an experiment to test it. You can do it with playing cards and a friend who knows the cards in the hole. But you need to repeat the experiment a number of times to get an approaching probability.

    • @martinsoltau6926
      @martinsoltau6926 Год назад

      @@klaus7443how can you start a sentence correctly sayin your initial chance is 2/3 to be wrong and then ending it with the conclusion that going away from that choice gives you no advantage? Weird.

  • @AaronWhiffin
    @AaronWhiffin Год назад +2

    The first one, my dad didn’t believe me, I was 2nd year maths and computing undergrad at uni.
    So I proved it mathematically, did it statistically with all combinations, and wrote a computer simulation to run it 1,000,000 times… all agreed that changing doors is best as no new information has been added.

    • @philip5940
      @philip5940 Год назад

      I've heard it before where someone says they proved it on a computer. I'd suggest that you already biased your initial conditions . It's a 50/50 chance. The problem posed is the probability of success of picking a concealed object when given two choices. Forget about the razzmatazz and music and audience reactions.

    • @AaronWhiffin
      @AaronWhiffin Год назад +1

      @@philip5940 I also proved it mathematically. And it's not, that's the point of the video

    • @philip5940
      @philip5940 Год назад

      @@AaronWhiffin the probability of success in picking a concealed object when given two choices is 50/50 . It's always been so . There's no such thing as magic . The events prior to and during the decision making do not change anything concerning the abstract of the decision making .

    • @AaronWhiffin
      @AaronWhiffin Год назад +1

      @@philip5940 Tell me you don't understand the video without saying it hahaha

    • @Michael_Arnold
      @Michael_Arnold Год назад

      @philip5940 You have a blind spot in this, Philip. Yes, a choice between two is a 50/50 choice. BUT:
      When you pick the first curtain, it has 1/3 chance of being correct.
      Meanwhile...
      *The other two curtains together* have 2/3 chance of holding the jackpot.
      The host removing one non-jackpot curtain of these two is just a detail, a clarification, of what is in this second 'set'. That 'side of the equation' is still 2/3 .

  • @darrenbillups1322
    @darrenbillups1322 20 дней назад

    As a maths school teacher I set up an experiment to check the Monty Hall problem. Half the class were told to play the game and they HAD to swap. The other half of the class had to stick. The results were very close to 66% and 33%

  • @Arbeitenification
    @Arbeitenification Год назад +4

    This is an imprecise formulation of the Monty Hall problem. It is imperative to state that the host knows what is hidden behind each curtain and that he has no choice whether to give you a preview or not.

    • @scottparker1741
      @scottparker1741 26 дней назад

      I don’t think you understand the Monty problem

  • @berniezenis4876
    @berniezenis4876 Год назад +24

    Monty Hall Problem: The reveal is irrelevant (in a sense). Imagine the game slightly differently. You pick a curtain just like in the regular game. Then you are given the option to stay with the single curtain or you can switch to BOTH the other two curtains. That is, if (you switch and) the big prize is behind either other curtain, you win the big prize. What do you do? Your initial curtain still only has 1/3 chance of having the big prize. The chance it is behind either of the other curtains is still 2/3. The odds didn't change (in a sense).

    • @Vaeldarg
      @Vaeldarg Год назад +4

      Yeah, the bad logic comes in that the extra 1/3 chance was added to the 2nd curtain in the video's example, but that's only because in the math it could only be added to 1 of the 2 remaining curtains. In reality, you still wouldn't know which curtain became more likely (the 2/3 chance) to have the $1M behind it.

    • @gobblinal
      @gobblinal Год назад +4

      That's an excellent way to describe the problem!

    • @glennmartin6492
      @glennmartin6492 Год назад +1

      I remember reading about the Monty Hall problem when I was young. The article said that the chance of the other option being right remained two thirds even as one of the curtains was eliminated but never bothered explaing why. It was so frustrating.

    • @scottishadonis
      @scottishadonis Год назад +1

      Yes I agree, it’s a common misconception of probability, I have actually applied this method to various “betting” situations and guess what? I lost 6 times out 7. I actually studied probability when doing my BSc in Electronic Engineering and touched on it more during my MSc. It’s actually a very common misconception and understanding of quantum physics.

    • @Dan-yk6sy
      @Dan-yk6sy Год назад

      I like it.

  • @PaulCotter0
    @PaulCotter0 Год назад +1

    It would be an interesting psych experiment to have two groups do the Monty Hall, but tell one group to pick the one they think has the prize, and second group to be picking a punishment and see how often they switch.

  • @VIKDR1
    @VIKDR1 Год назад +2

    The "Monty Hall Problem" came about because of a question to Marylin Vos Savant. Somebody asked if it was better to switch or keep their original choice, though with one prize, and 2 with essentially nothing, and she proceeded to say it's best to change it. She was inundated with mail about the whole thing, including from mathematics professors who said she was wrong. (Many of them sent a second letter asking her not to publish their first letters, or keep their names out of it, after figuring out they were wrong.)
    Mrs. Savant followed up and even had a bunch of kids create an experiment where they run multiple tests using the same parameters, and the results all supported what she had said.
    She gave a similar example to the one above, with a hundred curtains.
    Since she was the one who originated this and gave the correct answer which confused the "experts" at first, her name should be included here.

    • @philip5940
      @philip5940 Год назад

      Her answer is to be expected from the mind of a person conditioned to answering IQ questions. The correct answer is indeed 50/50 and not ⅓ to ⅔ . Interestingly Tibees does a video where she answers an IQ question as might a person with an IQ of 300 by coming up with a polynomial equation to generate the pattern presented for the trend given for which the next step in the series needs to be given . Her polynomial equation yields the original starting point instead of an obvious intuitive next number for the series.

    • @stephenolan5539
      @stephenolan5539 Год назад

      ​@@philip5940
      It is not 50/50.
      Why would it be 50/50?

    • @hughobyrne2588
      @hughobyrne2588 Год назад

      Have you *read* what vos Savant wrote? She had a web page about the whole thing, though it seems you can now only find it in archives. In her own words, "So let’s look at it again, remembering that the original answer defines certain conditions, the most significant of which is that the host always opens a losing door on purpose".
      The answer defines the conditions for answering the question? No. The question defines the conditions for answering the question. If the answer is defining the conditions for reaching the answer, it's circular reasoning.

    • @VIKDR1
      @VIKDR1 Год назад

      @@hughobyrne2588
      Wrong. In order to always open a losing door, whoever opens that door has to know which is a loosing door.
      But again, the video above shows the answer is correct, and a lot of grade schools participated in an experiment where it worked. There are even web pages that demonstrate this. I shared one link, but apparently that post vanished. I did 200 tests where I always changed, and hit real close to a 66% win rate.

    • @VIKDR1
      @VIKDR1 Год назад

      @@philip5940
      Not sure what happened to my response, possibly removed because it had a link. But the link was to where you could test it yourself. There are a few web pages set up to test this, and I ran 200 samples, always choosing to switch, and won real close to 66%.
      Also watch the video I am responding to. They say it works.

  • @martonhederics6787
    @martonhederics6787 Год назад +4

    The "maths might not be real" theory actually messed with my brain

  • @danfreedse
    @danfreedse Год назад +4

    Thanks, great episode! I love maths

  • @friendgray1
    @friendgray1 14 дней назад +2

    I’m not passing on a 2/3 chance for some essential potassium

  • @evelynbeverley2277
    @evelynbeverley2277 Год назад +1

    I never understood how the Monty Hall problem worked until I saw the Parade Magazine chart solution, and the importance of the "intervention" of the Monty Hall person. The key idea is that the person revealing what is behind one of the curtains follows the rule that they cannot show you the prize. They have to show you the other bad choice. They cannot show you what is behind the curtain you picked either. This is the key idea that changes the odds of winning if you switch your choice. There are three possible outcomes. If you keep your choice, only in one scenario you are right, other two choices are wrong. But in the other two scenarios you are wrong in your first choice. That means that two out of three times you have eliminated the lesser choice. Monty then shows you the other curtain, and it cannot be the prize. Monty has now, two out of three times, shown (or proved) to you which curtain has the prize. It is not the one he showed you, and two out of three times it is not the one you picked. So two out of three times it is the other curtain. If you can switch you will therefore win two out of three times! Your odds of winning when switching are 66%.

    • @barryschwarz
      @barryschwarz 16 дней назад

      In what game show in the world is the big prize given away at random. i'm mystified as to why people hear the words "game show" and don't immediately understand the host doesn't just give the prize away at random, but makes a selection that gives the contestant a choice, and thus intrigue for the viewer.

    • @cigmorfil4101
      @cigmorfil4101 15 дней назад

      @@barryschwarz Try 3-2-1.
      In it the contestants were given clues as to what each prize was. There were 5 clues given one at a time, but once 3 were on the table the contestants had to get rid of one. The prizes ranged from the big main prize down to a dustbin booby prize (and yes, it was won on a few occasions). If they could not work out the clues, they would have to pick one at random to get rid of. Either by chance or by not working out the clues properly they could end up rejecting the big main prize.
      Although not exactly giving the main prize at random, it did have the chance that the main prize would be eliminated, possibly by random chance.

    • @barryschwarz
      @barryschwarz 15 дней назад

      @@cigmorfil4101 No, that doesn't fit the bill. I don't know any game show that would give away a million due to a random choice made by the host. And it the context of a game show, it just doesn't make sense.
      I think what actually happens is that people make the common intuitive choice that the remaining two doors are a 50/50 chance, and then try to justify their intuition (eve when they figure out it was incorrect) by arguing post-hoc that the host might give away the prize at random (every 3rd game!).
      You see various iterations of this post-hoc justification. Some people argue that it's 50/50 if a new contestant steps in after the first choice, and doesn't see which door was first chosen. Well, yes, now the choice is 50/50, but why change the format of the game to make that argument?
      I'm sure there are people who hear the words "game show" and actually imagine that the host might pick a door at random, often revealing the $1,000,000 prize. But I doubt this is the majority of people. And the riddle infers the same action each time, it does not infer in any way that the host might reveal the prize... and then ask the contestant to "stick or switch?"
      No, it doesn't maker sense.

  • @justsomeboyprobablydressed9579
    @justsomeboyprobablydressed9579 Год назад +4

    Everyone always states the Monty Hall problem incorrectly. You're leaving out critical information. You have to tell us that (A) The host is fully aware of what's behind each curtain at the start, (B) the host always chooses to reveal a curtain, and (C) when he reveals one of the other two curtains, he always does so, using his prior knowledge, in a way to avoid revealing the grand prize. Also, the Monty Hall problem doesn't qualify as a "mathematical discovery."

    • @hughobyrne2588
      @hughobyrne2588 Год назад

      Many of the people putting forward the "switching is better!" idea are doing so, directly or indirectly, because of the article written by Marilyn vos Savant, in response to the letter written by Craig F. Whitaker. She had a whole web page devoted to this one problem, though you can now only find it in archives. You know what she wrote?
      "So let’s look at it again, remembering that the original answer defines certain conditions, the most significant of which is that the host always opens a losing door on purpose."
      These are her words. She straight up says she's using circular reasoning. The answer does not define the conditions for getting from the question to the (correct) answer. The *question* defines the conditions for getting from the question to the correct answer. If the answer is defining the conditions to get to the answer, that's circular reasoning.

    • @MijinLaw
      @MijinLaw 26 дней назад

      Yep I joined the comments to state this also. The monty hall problem is indeed counter intuitive, and it's not helped in this video by not only not explaining that it's the way monty chooses a curtain to reveal that's significant, but not even mentioning it in the description of the puzzle.

    •  День назад

      "You're leaving out critical information."
      Exactly! And even worse, the experiment in the video is slightly different to the original MHP. As there are three different prizes, it means there are more strategies the host can follow.
      Depending on what strategy, the probabilities changes.
      For example, the host could follow the strategy "reveal the door with the lowest prize". If that is the case, switching doors in the video example is only 50%.
      Another example that shows that knowing the strategy is important, is to imagine the guest is a monkey. For the monkey, the big prize is the banana. Should the monkey also always switch doors to improve the change to get the highest prize?

    • @MijinLaw
      @MijinLaw День назад

      @@hughobyrne2588 If it were circular reasoning it wouldn't need explaining. But it does, it's counter intuitive to most people (I'll admit, like 99% of people, I didn't get this puzzle when I first heard it)

  • @Shadow_banned_again
    @Shadow_banned_again Год назад +4

    Monty Hall problem originated from Marylin vos Savant. She originally faced quite a backlash even among University Professors. And we see who was right.

    • @hughobyrne2588
      @hughobyrne2588 Год назад +1

      I think it's fair to say the originator of the problem is the person who asked the problem, Craig F. Whitaker. He wrote a letter to vos Savant while she was writing a regular column in Parade magazine.
      In Whitaker's letter, as in the question as phrased at the beginning of the video, there is no indication that a compulsion is placed on the game show host to always reveal a door with the booby prize, a critical component in the chain of logic which leads to the conclusion "it's better to switch".

  • @dominicmillns5856
    @dominicmillns5856 Год назад +1

    There’s two kinds of people in the world.
    1. Those that can extrapolate information from incomplete data
    2.

  • @ldfahrni
    @ldfahrni 13 дней назад

    One key for me understanding the first problem is that Monty NEVER opens the curtain with the million bucks, leaving you a choice of the zonk you picked or the zonk you could switch to, because he knows where the million is. He's giving you MORE information which you ignore at your peril.